Problem 17 Interpret the following symboliz... [FREE SOLUTION] (2024)

Chapter 6: Problem 17

Interpret the following symbolized arguments in light of the eight argumentforms presented in this section. In some cases a symbolized argument must berewritten using commutativity or double negation before it becomes an instanceof one of these forms. Those not having a named form are invalid. $$\begin{array}{l} K \supset \sim C \\ \frac{C}{\sim K} \end{array}$$

Short Answer

Expert verified

The argument \(K \supset \sim C, \ therefore \sim K\) represents the fallacy of Denying the Antecedent, which is an invalid argument form.

Step by step solution

01

Identify the Given Argument Form

The provided symbolic argument is in the form of a conditional statement followed by an assertion. In formal logic, we use various named argument forms to classify such statements. The given argument is: If K then not C, symbolized as: \( K \supset \sim C \).

02

Recognize the Conclusion's Relationship to the Premise

The argument concludes with \( \sim K \) (not K). The conclusion seems to be the denial of the antecedent in the premise. To properly analyze if the argument is valid, we must consider the valid forms of argument and check for any indirect equivalences.

03

Compare With Known Valid Argument Forms

The given argument doesn't instantly appear to fit any of the eight named valid argument forms directly. These include forms like Modus Ponens, Modus Tollens, and Hypothetical Syllogism, among others.

04

Transform the Argument if Necessary

There's no need to rewrite the argument using commutativity or double negation since the given argument is already in a relevant form to compare with the named forms.

05

Check for Invalid Argument Forms

The argument structure resembles the fallacy known as 'Denying the Antecedent,' which has the following form: If P then Q, Not P, therefore Not Q. This is recognized as an invalid argument form since the truth of the consequent is not logically dependent on the antecedent being false.

Key Concepts

These are the key concepts you need to understand to accurately answer the question.

Conditional Statement

A conditional statement is a logical statement that has two parts: an antecedent (the 'if' part) and a consequent (the 'then' part). It's commonly represented in the form If P, then Q, or symbolically as \(P \rightarrow Q\). The conditional statement establishes a relationship which holds that if the first part is true, then the second part is expected to be true as well.

For example, a conditional statement can be something like 'If it rains, then the ground will be wet.' Here, the antecedent is 'it rains', and the consequent is 'the ground will be wet'. However, note that if the antecedent is false, it doesn't necessarily provide information about the consequent. That means even if it doesn't rain, the ground might still be wet for other reasons.

Modus Ponens

Modus Ponens is a common form of valid argument. It can be stated as: If P then Q, P is asserted, therefore Q must be true. Symbolically, the form looks like \(P \rightarrow Q\), \(P\), hence \(Q\).

This valid form of argument takes a conditional statement and asserts that since the antecedent is true, the consequent necessarily follows. For example, if we know that 'If it rains, the ground gets wet', and we know that 'It is raining', we can deduce that 'The ground gets wet'.

Modus Tollens

Modus Tollens is also a valid argument form, which is the inverse of Modus Ponens. The form goes as follows: If P then Q, Not Q is asserted, therefore P must not be true. In symbolic form, this is represented as \(P \rightarrow Q\), \(eg Q\), hence \(eg P\).

Using the same example as before, if we know that 'If it rains, the ground gets wet', but we see that 'The ground is not wet', we can deduce that 'It has not rained'. It negates the consequent and thereby denies the antecedent, one of the rare cases where denying the consequent is logically valid.

Denying the Antecedent

The fallacy called Denying the Antecedent is an invalid argument form and often mistaken for a valid deductive argument. This fallacy takes the form: If P then Q, Not P is asserted, therefore Not Q must be true. Symbolically, \(P \rightarrow Q\), \(eg P\), hence \(eg Q\).

This form is invalid because the falsity of the antecedent does not necessarily lead to the falsity of the consequent. For instance, 'If it rains, the ground gets wet', but the statement 'It did not rain' does not warrant the conclusion that 'The ground is not wet', as there might be other reasons for the ground to be wet.

Hypothetical Syllogism

Hypothetical Syllogism is an argument form that involves two conditional statements and leads to a conclusion. It follows the structure: If P then Q, If Q then R, therefore If P then R. In symbols, \(P \rightarrow Q\), \(Q \rightarrow R\), hence \(P \rightarrow R\).

For example, using our recurring theme, think of the statements 'If it rains, then the ground gets wet' and 'If the ground gets wet, the grass grows'. From these two, we can conclude that 'If it rains, the grass grows', combining the two conditional statements into a single conclusion.

Valid Argument

A valid argument is one where if the premises are true, the conclusion necessarily follows; it's impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. Validity is about the logical strength of the argument, not necessarily the truth of the premises or conclusion.

For instance, Modus Ponens and Modus Tollens are classic examples of valid arguments because they adhere to the correct logical form. However, validity does not claim that the premises or the conclusion reflects reality, only that the conclusion logically follows from the premises.

Invalid Argument

An invalid argument is the opposite of a valid one. If the structure of the argument allows for the possibility that the premises can be true while the conclusion is false, then the argument is invalid. The reasoning does not hold up logically, and the conclusion is not a necessary outcome from the premises.

For example, Denying the Antecedent and Affirming the Consequent are types of invalid arguments. They represent a misunderstanding of how conditions work in logic and lead to false conclusions even if the premises given seem true. It's crucial to identify and avoid these forms when constructing logical arguments.

This website uses cookies to improve your experience. We'll assume you're ok with this, but you can opt-out if you wish. Accept

Problem 17 Interpret the following symboliz... [FREE SOLUTION] (2024)

References

Top Articles
Latest Posts
Article information

Author: Reed Wilderman

Last Updated:

Views: 5593

Rating: 4.1 / 5 (72 voted)

Reviews: 87% of readers found this page helpful

Author information

Name: Reed Wilderman

Birthday: 1992-06-14

Address: 998 Estell Village, Lake Oscarberg, SD 48713-6877

Phone: +21813267449721

Job: Technology Engineer

Hobby: Swimming, Do it yourself, Beekeeping, Lapidary, Cosplaying, Hiking, Graffiti

Introduction: My name is Reed Wilderman, I am a faithful, bright, lucky, adventurous, lively, rich, vast person who loves writing and wants to share my knowledge and understanding with you.